Abstract
David Hume is one of the classical moral sentimentalists, famously claiming that moral judgments are constituted by a certain kind of feeling, or moral sentiment. In this paper, however, I argue that Hume’s moral theory ultimately separates moral judgment from sentiment and, consequently, places the nature of moral judgment in language. To begin with, keeping in mind the so-called Moral Attitude Problem, I show that it is unclear until the end what kind of sentiment Hume’s “moral sentiment” is. Then, I will examine what is really connected with moral judgment in Hume’s theory in the following steps. First, it is confirmed that some moral judgments based on the “general point of view” that Hume introduces are merely verbal judgments without any perceptible sentiments. However, since it is possible that moral language—a set of moral terms—may shoulder the sentimental aspect of such verbal judgments, I trace back the genealogy of moral judgments to see what kind of sentiment was tied to moral language. It is found that when people repeatedly experience that agreement in their reactions to a person is achieved by ignoring the feelings of their sentiments, they establish the general point of view, based on which moral language is created. This origin of moral language suggests that it cannot have any emotional meaning. Thus, insofar as some of what Hume counts as moral judgments do not involve substantive sentiment in any sense, sentiment does not determine the extension of moral judgment. When Hume nevertheless says that moral judgment is constituted by sentiment, that sentiment is merely a kind of fiction, retrospectively assumed from the use of moral language. Finally, given the above, I further argue that it is language that essentially determines the extension of moral judgment in Hume’s moral philosophy.
Keywords
David Hume, Moral sentimentalism, Moral attitude problem, General point of view, Moral language
References
- Abramson, K. (1999). Correcting Our Sentiments about Hume’s Moral Point of View. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 37, 333–361.
- Baier, A. C. (2006). How Wide is Hume’s Circle? (A question raised by the exchange between Erin I. Kelly and Louis E. Loeb, Hume Studies, November 2004). Hume Studies, 32(1), 113–117.
- Björnsson, G., & McPherson, T. (2014). Moral Attitudes for Non-Cognitivists: Solving the Specification Problem. Mind, 123(489), 1–38.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in Quasi-Realism. Oxford University Press.
- Brown, C. (1994). From Spectator to Agent: Hume’s Theory of Obligation. Hume Studies, 20(1), 19–36.
- Brown, C. (2001). Is the General Point of View the Moral Point of View? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(1), 197–203.
- Carlson, A. (2014). The Moral Sentiments in Hume’s Treatise: A Classificatory Problem. Hume Studies, 40(1), 73–94.
- Cohon, R. (2008). Hume’s Morality: Feeling and Fabrication. Oxford University Press.
- Garrett, D. (1997). Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
- Garrett, D. (2001a). Precis of Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(1), 185–189.
- Garrett, D. (2001b). Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(1), 205–215.
- Hume, D. ([1739–40] 2007). A Treatise of Human Nature, 2 vols. (D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton, Eds.). Oxford University Press.
- Hume, D. ([1751] 1998). An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (T. L. Beauchamp, Ed.). Oxford University Press.
- Hume, D. ([1777] 1985). Essays Moral, Political and Literary (E. F. Miller, Ed.). Liberty Fund.
- Joyce, R. (2009). Expressivism, Motivation Internalism, and Hume. In Pigden, C. R. (Ed.), Hume on Motivation and Virtue (pp. 30–56). Palgrave Macmillan.
- Kauppinen, A. (2010). What Makes a Sentiment Moral? In Shafer-Landau, R. (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 5 (pp. 225–256). Oxford University Press.
- Korsgaard, C. M. (1999). The General Point of View: Love and Moral Approval in Hume’s Ethics. Hume Studies, 25(1&2), 3–41.
- Köhler, S. (2013). Do Expressivists Have an Attitude Problem? Ethics, 123(3), 479–507.
- King, J. T. (1976). The Place of the Language of Morals in Hume’s Second Enquiry. In Livingston, D., & King, J. T. (Eds.), Hume: A Re-Evaluation. Fordham University Press.
- Mackie, J. L. (1980). Hume’s Moral Theory. Routledge.
- Magri, T. (1996). Natural Obligation and Normative Motivation in Hume’s Treatise. Hume Studies, 22(2), 231–254.
- McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, Value, and Reality. Harvard University Press.
- Merli, D. (2008). Expressivism and the Limits of Moral Disagreement. The Journal of Ethics, 12(1), 25–55.
- Miller, A. (1998). Emotivism and the Verification Principle. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 98, 103–124.
- Miller, A. (2013). Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd edition. Polity.
- Radcliffe, E. S. (2022). Hume on the Nature of Morality (Elements in Ethics). Cambridge University Press.
- Slote, M. (2010). Moral Sentimentalism. Oxford University Press.
- Smith, M. (2001). Some Not-Much-Discussed Problems for Non-Cognitivism in Ethics. Ratio, 14(2), 93–115.
- Stewart, C. (1976). The Moral Point of View. Philosophy, 51(196), 177–187.